Laughter and the Word — Stern
Documents
Keywords
Share
Conventional wisdom holds that modernity ushered in an end to the age of the legal spectacle. Public gallows and whipping posts gave way to the forced seclusion of supermax prisons. The charisma of medieval sovereigns receded, in turn, before the spell cast by personal smartphone devices, with which the contemporary hero of classical economics makes “orders” from the privacy of bed. Cultural historians have long contrasted the increasing visibility of scientific trials in modernity to their legal counterparts, tracing how labs transformed from chambers tucked in the basements of museums into public demonstrations of fact. At least since Foucault’s Discipline and Punish (1975), however, it has been a truism in cultural studies that legal procedures took the opposite course: while sentencing and execution remained public after 1300, historians have contended, other aspects of the process retreated from sight, preparing the ground for the emergence of an elusive yet ubiquitous, Kafkaesque style of law whose force is all the more sinister for remaining hidden.
Enter Julie Stone Peters’ Law as Performance. In this commanding, formidably entertaining, and meticulously argued study, Peters argues that law has never been reducible to divine will, the whim of a sovereign, or the expression of ecclesiastical or secular power. Nor did it ever vanish from the public eye. For the sources she examines, from court records to handbooks by ancient, medieval and early modern philosophers of rhetoric to visual representations of trial proceedings and more, Peters demonstrates that at least until 1678, law in Europe remained a scene: of passion, persuasion, seduction, violence, and comedy, dependent—however ambivalently—on techniques from the dramatic arts. Her book challenges a scholarly consensus that the emotionally charged trials of the later middle ages tapered out into rituals of sacrifice and redemption performed before passive spectators. Instead, she shows, early modern courts remained intense, even anarchic spaces where audiences helped guide judicial opinion, and theorists of law continued to emphasize retribution, deterrence, and the use of violence to treat social wounds.
Peters’ study not only unearths neglected sources that crystallize European law’s interpenetration with the arts before the 17th century. It also investigates the long jurisprudential tradition of confronting the importance of theatrical techniques to what she calls law’s “art of the real” [1]. She shows that the ambivalence legal theorists expressed about the relevance of affect to the doing of law was not peripheral to jurisprudence but, on the contrary, at the dead center of these theorists’ attempts to differentiate their discipline. By exposing the role of art in law’s capacity to engage reaches of experience not conventionally associated with rational thought, Peters recasts the law’s reputation for dispassion as a stage effect achieved through the very artistic means it disavows. Hers is that rare intervention that responds to an enduring problem by changing its terms. It presses the question, “What is the law’s relationship to art?” into another: “What kind of art is law?”
“[T]he problem,” Peters contends in her discussion of the classical foundations of early modern jurisprudence, “is not that theatre rouses emotions dangerous to the status quo (as in the textbook versions of Plato and Aristotle); it is that it rouses emotions that are insufficiently dangerous” (53). The claim bears repeating: the problem for legal theorists of antiquity was not that art rouses dangerous emotions, Peters argues, but that art is insufficiently dangerous. Peters is doing more here, I would suggest, than taking on Popperian readings of Plato that constrain his perspective on poetry to his warnings about theatrocracy (rule by theater) in the Laws. Attending closely to the sources behind this consensus—i.e. Plato’s Laws, Aristotle’s Rhetoric in concert with his writings on music, and the works of three other widely respected Greek orators—she shows that Plato’s exile of the poets coexisted with an emphasis both he and his contemporaries placed on the political utility of affect. The implicit suggestion here is that classical rhetoric, read on its own terms, paints the law—somewhat counterintuitively, given its notorious monotony—as sufficiently dangerous theater, theater capable of galvanizing citizens to act. This, sufficiently dangerous theater works for the same reason art works: it uses techniques of showing, rather than saying, to move audiences, engaging the unconscious layers of experience operative in judgement. It should come as no surprise, then, that the body—through tears, screaming, laughter, and even, in the case of 15th century German townswoman, Catharina Arndes, who summoned the courage to moon a judge, partial nudity—played a starring role in early modern trials.
I would wager that the emphasis on bodily affect Peters recovers from these sources has implications for our so-called “post-truth” era of TikTok, on the one hand, and democratic decline on the other. At the same time, it complements a powerfully influential story about the nature of law while stretching it in key ways. In “Violence and the Word” (1986), legal scholar Robert Cover draws on Elaine Scarry’s theory of torture to frame violence as a legal technique for marking the boundary of a subject’s normative world. In torture, Cover maintains, the subject cannot speak, can no longer sing the song of the polity, just make the noises of a body trying to survive. This is one way that, for Cover, torture exemplifies what he calls the law’s “jurispathic” impulse, a check on “jurisgenesis”—his hallmark concept, the making of meaning through narrative. Legal violence, for Cover, stakes out the limits of a subject’s world by casting her voice out of the fold of speech and into the wilderness of sound.
Cover paints a picture of law as a rhythm of burgeoning and contracting meaning, narrative proliferation that is constantly pruned back down by the law’s homicidal focus on the body. It’s here that Law as Performance intervenes. In discussions of legal spectacles, it’s become a commonplace to focus on spectacular punishments in particular, and there is certainly no shortage of evidence for the violent uses of law to be found in the pages this book. At the same time, Peters demonstrates that the law’s relationship to the body has never been reducible to the infliction of harm. It engaged the body in comic and ridiculous ways, too, eliciting visceral responses from audience members in turn. What Cover situated as “outside” normativity—bodily experience, in all its vulnerability, anarchy, and waywardness—Law as Performance establishes in other words as part and parcel to the doing of law.
Acknowledging both the role of bodily irreverence in law’s art of reality and the violent excesses of this—indeed, sufficiently dangerous—art today is not, it seems to this reader, to succumb to cynicism. On the contrary, it’s to resist the pleasures of a naïve trust in the healing powers of narrative form. Time heals all wounds, but time is the wound, as the saying goes. Narratives do harm. By undermining a categorical distinction between legal meaning and legal violence, Peters’ argument brings a vitally unsentimental perspective to a moment in which, as Roberto Esposito has recently observed, a dialectic between a progressive faith in the power of dynamic “movements” and conservative insistence on a static “rule of law” has threatened to monopolize our political vocabulary. For both the right and the left today, law at large is said to be losing credibility—the left defends democracy even as it’s pessimistic about the opinion of the majority to guide us safely through the threats of fascism, on the one hand, and climate change, on the other; while the right has lost faith in the very processes that register the opinion of the majority. At the same time, the institution of the theater remains, for both camps, in full flower. We are living in a moment in which anyone with a smartphone can amass an audience of hundreds in a few weeks’ time, in which the corporations administrating these displays sustain themselves on a libidinal economy of affects called “likes,” and in which the tap of a thumb can be felt around the world. The ease of being seen—and being seen to be seen—through the affordances of social media today has indeed worked to bolster democratic forms of life even as it’s helped to poison trust in their implementation.
Are we still medieval? That’s a question for our speakers. I have suggested that by substituting one ancient question—“what is the law’s relationship to art?”—with another—“what kind of art is law?”—Law as Performance has opened up a fresh response to an urgent question of our time. How can it be that the crowd—the demos of democracy—is losing its voice at the very moment when, through the spread of social networks, its voice has never been louder? It sounds like a paradox, but within the intellectual horizon of this book, there is no contradiction. Performative technologies like Twitter and TikTok are continuous with law’s history, Peters shows, iterations of the “rule of the audience” we have always recognized (36). Whether we like to admit it or not, we are still like the ancient playwrights, trapped in aesthetic combat on virtual stages. It’s a terrifying vision, but it’s a gently comic one, too, and one of the many contributions of this captivating book is to revive the possibility of laughing with the law. The show must go on. That’s an order!
Notes
- Julie Peters. Law as Performance. Oxford University Press (2022), 86[↑]